A medicine of personal meaning does not necessarily depend on health or healing
Main Article Content
Abstract
Article Details
References
Hanson, M., Callahan, D. (1999). Project report. The goals of medicine: setting new priorities. In: The Goals of Medicine: The Forgotten Issue in Health Care Reform. (eds. M. Hanson, D. Callahan D.), pp. 1-54. Washington DC: Georgetown University Press.
Buetow, S. (2002). Beyond evidence-based medicine: bridge-building a medicine of meaning. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 8, 103-108.
World Health Organization (WHO). (1948). Official records of the World Health Organization. Geneva: WHO.
Flew, A., Priest, S. (2002). A Dictionary of Philosophy. London: Pan Books.
Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science 44, 542-573.
Nordenfelt, L. (1995). On the Nature of Health: An Action-Theoretic Aproach. Dordecht: Kluwer.
Pörn, I. (1993). Health and Adaptedness. Theoretical Medicine 14, 295-303.
De Grazia, D. (2005). Enhancement technologies and human identity. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 30, 261-283.
Chan, S. (2008). Enhancement, evolution and the possible futures of humanity. EMBO Reports 9, S70-S74.
Greely, H., Sahakian, B., Harris, J., Kessler, R. C., Gazzaniga, M., Campbell, P., Farah, M.J. (2008). Towards responsible use of cognitive-enhancing drugs by the healthy. Nature 456, 702-705.
Sadler, J., Jotterand, F., Lee, S., Inrig, S. (2009). Can medicalization be good? Situating medicalization within bioethics. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 30, 411-425.
Frankl, V. (1962). Man's Search for Meaning. An Introduction to Logotherapy. Boston: Beacon Press.
Buetow, S. (2007). Non-attendance for health care: when rational beliefs collide. Sociological Review 55, 592-610.
Muldoon, M., Barger, S., Flory, J., Manuck, S. (1998). What are quality of life measurements measuring? British Medical Journal 316, 542-545.
Veatch, R., Miller, F. (2001). The internal morality of medicine: An introduction. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26, 555-557.
McLaughlin, L., Braun, K. (1998). Asian and Pacific Islander cultural values: considerations for health care decision-making. Health and Social Work 23, 116-126.
McMillan, R. (1995). Responsibility to or for in the physician-patient relationship. Journal of Medical Ethics 21, 112-115.
Madder, H. (1997). Existential autonomy: why patients should make their own choices. Journal of Medical Ethics 23, 221-225.
Tilburt, J. (2011). Shared Decision Making After MacIntyre. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36, 148-169.
D'Amico, R. (2007). Disease and the concept of supervenience. Philosophy and Medicine 90, 35-45.
Ioannidis, J. (2005). Why most published research findings are false. PLoS Medicine 2, (8), e124.
Upshur, R. E. G. (2000). Seven characteristics of medical evidence. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 6, 93-97.
Elwyn, G., Buetow, S., Hibbard, J., Wensing, M. (2007). Respecting the subjective: quality measurement from the patient's perspective. British Medical Journal 335, 1021-1022.
Frankl, V. (1963). Man's search for meaning: an introduction to logotherapy. Boston: Beacon Press.
Mezzich, J., Snaedal, J., van Weel, C., Heath, I. (2009).
The International Network for Person-centred Medicine. Background and first steps. World Medical Journal 55, 104-107.
Glenn, L. (2003). Biotechnology at the Margins of Personhood: An Evolving Legal Paradigm Journal of Evolution and Technology 13. Available at: http://jetpress.org/volume13/glenn.html (last accessed 2 August 2011).
Frankfurt, H. (1971). Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. Journal of Philosophy 68, 5-20.
Reznek, M. (1987). The nature of disease. New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Brudney, D., Lantos, J. (In press). Agency and authenticity: Which value grounds patient choice? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics.
Jonas, H. (1984). The imperative of responsibility: in search of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Boudon, R. (2003). Beyond rational choice theory. Annual Review of Sociology 29, 1-21.
Williams, W. (1978). Behavioural anomalies in patients and doctors. II Secondary gain, or the advantages of being 'sick'. In: Psychiatry for the non-Psychiatrist. (ed. J. Ellard), pp. 167-172. Sydney: Geigy Pharmaceuticals.
Parsons, T. (1951). The social system. Glencoe IL: Free Press.
Apter, M. (1982). Reversal theory: Motivation, Emotion and Personality. New York: Routledge.
Buetow, S. (1995). What do general practitioners and their patients want from general practice and are they receiving it? A framework. Social Science and Medicine 40, 213-221.
Jarrett, L. (1999). Nourishing destiny. Stockbridge, Mass: Spirit Path Press.
Parens, E., ed. (1998). Enhancing human traits: ethical and social implications. Washington D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
Edwards, J. (2000). Passion, activity, and "the care of the self". Hastings Center Report 30, 31-34.
Hanson, M. (1999). Indulging anxiety: human enhancement from a Protestant perspective. Christian Bioethics 5, 121-138.
Wolbring, G. (2005). The triangle of enhancement medicine, disabled people, and the concept of health: a new challenge for HTA, health research, and health policy. Edmonton: Alberta Heritage Foundation for Medical Research.
Buetow, S., Roland, M. (1999). Clinical governance: bridging the gap between managerial and clinical approaches to quality of care. Quality in Health Care 8, 184-190.
Heath, I. (2007). Family medicine should focus on the 'sick': Affirmative position. In: Ideological Debates in Family Medicine. (eds. S. Buetow, T. Kenealy), pp. 73-81. New York: Nova Biomedical Books.
Caplan, A., Elliott, C. (2004). Is It ethical to use enhancement technologies to make us better than well? . PLOS Med;1(3):52. 1, (3), 172-175.
Pence, G. (1991). Virtue theory. In: A Companion to Ethics. (ed. P. Singer), pp. 249-258. Oxford: Blackwell.
Buetow, S., Elwyn, G. (2008). The window mirror: a new model of the patient-physician relationship. Open Medicine 2, E20-25.
Ginn, F., Demeritt, D. (2009). Nature: a contested concept. In: Key Concepts in Geography. (eds. N. Clifford N., S. Holloway S., S. Rice, G. Valentine), pp. 300-311. London: Sage.
Sandman, L., Munthe, C. (2010). Shared decision making, Paternalism and patient choice. Health Care Analysis. 18, 60-84.
McNutt, R. (2007). Shared decision-making: optional v mandatory autonomy of patients. Family medicine should support the optional autonomy of patients in decision-making: the negative argument. In: Ideological Debates in Family Medicine. (eds. S.Buetow, T. Kenealy), pp. 251-259. New York: Nova Science Publishers.
McNutt, R. (2004). Shared medical decision making. Problems, process, progress. Journal of the American Medical Association 292, 2516-2518.
Emanuel, E. J., Emanuel, L. (1992). Four models of the physician-patient relationship. Journal of the American Medical Association 267, 2221-2226.
Seedhouse, D. (2006). Health: The foundations for achievement. Chichester: John Wiley and Sons.
Feldman, M. (2011). From the Editors’ Desk: Physician Heal Thyself. Journal of General Internal Medicine 26, 823.
Williams, B. (1994). Patient satisfaction: A valid concept? Social Science and Medicine 38, 509-516.
Veatch, R. (1996). Modern vs. contemporary medicine: The patient-provider relation in the twenty-first century Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6, 366-370.
Patrick, J. (2008). Hippocratic medicine today. Available at: http://www.hippocraticregistry.com/index.html (last accessed 2 August 2011).
Savulescu, J. (1997). Liberal rationalism and medical decision-making. Bioethics 11, 115-129.
Buetow, S. (1998). Four strategies for negotiated care. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine 91, 199-201.
Buetow, S. (1999). Unsolicited GP advice against smoking: To give or not to give? Journal of Health Communication 4, 67-74.
Greene, J. (2007). Mixed methods in social inquiry. San Francisco: Wiley.
Chervenak, F., McCullough, L. (2009). Ethical distinction between direct and indirect referral for abortion. The Female Patient 34, 12, 46-48.