Problems of transparent medical risk communication using the example of mammography screening

Main Article Content

Christof Breitsameter

Abstract

The specific requirements of risk-laden decision situations pose an increasing challenge to medical ethics to establish normative risk communication models. Providing information about probabilities with which certain events will occur, however, is but one part of the ‘deal’. Medical education also means that risks are communicated in an understandable manner. Otherwise, the patient would indeed have information available but he or she would not be able to interpret and evaluate it correctly. Using the example of mammography screenings, this article describes problems of transparent medical risk communication and attempts to answer the question of how these difficulties may be overcome.

Article Details

Section
Clinical and Electronic Communication

References

Birnbacher, D., Wagner, B. (2003). Risiko. In: Bioethik. Eine Einführung (ed. M. Düwell, K. Steigleder), pp. 435-446. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

Hansson, S. O. (1996). What is philosophy of risk? Theoria 62, 169-186.

Brock, D. W. (1993). Life and death. Philosophical essays in biomedical ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Angell M. (2008). Industry-sponsored clinical research.A broken system. Journal of the American Medical Association 300, 1069-1071.

Braddock, C. H., Edwards, K. A., Hasenberg, N. M., Laidley, T. L. & Levinson, W. (1999). Informed decision making in outpatient practice: time to get back to basics. Journal of the American Medical Association 282, 2313-2320.

Breitsameter, C. (2009). Individualisierte Perfektion. Vom Wert der Werte. Paderborn: Schöningh.

Breitsameter, C. (2010). Medical decision making and communication of risks – an ethical perspective. Journal of Medical Ethics36, 349-352.

Brock, D. W. (1993). Life and death. Philosophical essays in biomedical ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Brody, H. (2005). The company we keep: why physicians should refuse to see pharmaceutical representatives. Annals of Family Medicine3, 82-85.

Charles, C., Gafni, A. & Whelan, T. (1997). Shared decision-making in the medical encounter: what does it mean? (Or it takes at least two to tango). Social Science & Medicine 44, 681-692.

Domenighetti, G., D’Avanzo, B., Egger, M., Berrino, F., Pernegerm, T. & Mosconi, P. (2003). Women’s perception of the benefits of mammography screening: population-based survey in four countries. International Journal of Epidemiology 32, 816-821.

Edwards, A. & Elwyn, G. (2000). How should ‘effectiveness’ of risk communication to aid patients’ decisions be judged? A review of the literature. Medical Decision Making 19, 428-434.

Egger, M., Bartlett, C. & Juni, P. (2001). Are randomised controlled trials in the BMJ different? British Medical Journal 323, 1253.

Elwyn, G., Edwards, A., Kinnersley, P. & Grol, R. (2000). Shared decision-making and the concept of equipoise: defining the ‘competences’ of involving patients in health care choices. The British Journal of General Practice50, 892-899.

Emanuel, E. & Emanuel, L. (1992). Four models of the physician-patient relationship. Journal of the American Medical Association267, 2221-2224.

Gigerenzer, G. (2002). Das Einmaleins der Skepsis. Über den richtigen Umgang mit Zahlen und Risiken. Berlin: Berliner Taschenbuch Verlag.

Gigerenzer, G., Gaissmaier, W., Kurz-Milcke, E., Schwartz, L. M. & Woloshin, S. (2007). Helping doctors and patients make sense of health statistics. Psychological Science in the Public Interest8, 53-96.

Quante, M. (2002). Personales Leben und menschlicher Tod. Personale Identität als Prinzip der biomedizinischen Ethik. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

Nida-Rümelin, J. (2005). Ethik des Risikos. In: Angewandte Ethik. Die Bereichsethiken und ihre theoretische Fundierung. Ein Handbuch. (ed. J. Nida-Rümelin), pp. 862-886. Second edition. Stuttgart: Kröner.

Gøtzsche, P. C. & Olsen, O. (2000). Is screening for breast cancer with mammography justifiable? Lancet 355, 129-134.